The Need for a Comparative Approach to Choice – of – law Problems

Frtedrich K. Juenger*

American confict of laws scholarship has a venerable comparative law tradition dating from the nineteenth-century works of Samuel Livermore and Justice Story. A twentieth-century «conflicts revolution,» however, has turned away from that tradition and, in the process, ignored the lessons comparison can teach Reinventing a forum-centered unilateralist approach, ihe "revolulionaries» seemed unawure ofthe faci thai their methodology, as well as the problems it poses,have long been known This Article urges a return to the comparative approach that used to characterize American conficts scholarship. That approach seems especially appropriate at a time when globalization increasingly brings foreign law problems lo our shores and gives rise to novel phenomena such as the new law merchant The perspective comparison affords can reveal the shortcomings of traditional methodologies, increuse the prospects oflaw reform, and enhance the level of multistate justice

Sumario: I. The Three Prongs of the Conflict of Laws. II. Four Approaches. A. Lex fori. B. Multilateralism. C. Unilateralism. D. The Substantive Law Approach E.Eclecticism III. The Choice-of-Law Evolution. A. The Statutist Approach. B. The Emergence of Multilateralism. C. Unilateralism Redivivus, IV. Comparative Perspectives. A. The Pitfalls of Disdaining Comparison. B. The Price of Parochialism,C.The Domestic Law Focus. D. The Efect of»Globalization». V. The Importance of Comparison. A .A Neglected Subject. B. The Role of State Courts. C. A Word in Conclusion.

It seems fitting to include in this tribute to Professor Athanassios Yiannopoulos,one of America’s foremost comparativists,some observations conceming the conflict of laws,a subject with which he is quite at home. Not only did he teach it for several years. but he also earmed a doctoral degree at the University of Cologne under the supervision of the distinguished German conflicts scholar Gerhard Kegel. I first met Professor Yiannopoulos because of our membership on the Board of Editors of the American Journal of Comparative Law.During the fall semester of 1989, when I was teaching at the Tulane University Law School as the Eason-Weinmann visiting professor,I had the pleasure of seeing him on a daily basis and talking with him about the conflict of laws, as well as maritime law, legal education and other topics of mutual interest. Ever since, we have remained in touch, meeting on numerous occasions in the United States as well as abroad. I am delighted to have this opportunity to pay my respects to an outstanding jurist,a good friend,and a fellow comparativist. My contribution to the Festschrifi in his honor is based on the Eason-Weinmann lecture Professor Yiannopoulos invited me to present in 1995.

1. The Three Prongs of the Confict of Laws

The conflict of laws comprises three distinct but interrelated subjects: jurisdiction, choice of law,and judgments recognition, This tripartite division reflects the questions facing counsel dealing with transactions that transcend the forum’s boundaries. Where, in the event of a dispute, should an action be brought; what law can the tribunal in which it is litigated be expected to apply; and will the tribunal’s decision be respected in other fora? In the United States, unlike in unitary legal systems,the conflict of laws serves a dual purpose: It is applicable to the resolution of problems arising from interstate transactions on the one hand and intemational transactions on the other. This dual purpose explains the subject’s name in American usage; elsewhere -not only in civil law jurisdictions but in countries where the common law reigns- the conflict of laws is usually referred to as «private intemational law.» The latter tenm, though it was coined by Justice Story.1 makes sense only in nations with a single private law, as opposed to federal systems such as the United States,where conflicts rules must, because of needs, do double duty. Clearly, as far as intemational conflict problems are concemed. comparative law is important, if only because the rules that «conflict» are those of different legal systems2 But even with respect to interstate problems, comparative law is a valuable tool: To look at conflicts rules and approaches that prevail abroad not only helps us gain perspective, but it can also fumish inspiration for domestic reforms. After all,one of the most important functions the comparative method serves is to offer an inventory of approaches to universal problems.3

Some time ago,I wrote an article that emphasized the need for a more global perspective with respect to the American law of jurisdiction, a field whose deplorable condition-so 1 argued-is largely due to the failure of American courts and scholars to avail themselves of the benefits the comparative method has to offer.4 Neglecting to look at such foreign models as the Brussels5 and Lugano Conventions,6 or even English practice,7 the United States Supreme Court has saddled us with a complex and confusing set of jurisdictional principles that offer little guidance to courts and counsel.8 The Court’s failure to establish clear and cogent precepts that help answer the simple question «can I sue here?» engenders much wasteful litigation and defeats the essential purpose of procedural rules, namely to promote the «just, speedy and inexpensive determination»9 of disputes. As I pointed out, no other legal system matches the complexity of our jurisdictional lore.10 Moreover,by constitutionalizing this field. the Court has effectively barred a major avenue for reform-treaties or conventions with foreign nations, which could substitute more orderly precepts for the current mess of state long-arm legislation and vacillating Supreme Court jurisprudence11. As is apparent, parochialism does exact a high price.

In marked contrast to the pitiful condition of the American law of jurisdiction,our law of judgments recognition is fairly common-sensical and liberal, largely because the common law has traditionally respected foreign court decisions.12 Originally,the civil law was equally liberal,13 but the rise of nation states focused attention on the notion of sovereignty,which does little to advance the interests of judgment creditors. A seventeenth century French enactment specifically denied effect to foreign judgments;14 other countries also increased barriers to recognition by establishing such requirements as reciprocity,15 rules protecting nationals,16 and the control of the initial forum’s choice-of-law determination.17 » The obstacles to judgments recognition prevailing abroad prompted our Supreme Court,in Hilton v. Guyor, to curtail the common law’s traditional liberality by adopting a reciprocity requirement.18 A number of state courts,however, refused to follow this precedent and by now most of the major states freely recognize judgments rendered in foreign countries.19 That enlightened trend owes something to the efforts of the late Dr. Nadelmann, a distinguished comparativist who served as the Reporter20 for the Uniform Foreign Money Judgments Recognition Act.21 This statute, one of the most important American conflict of laws enactments, has been adopted in a considerable number of states.22 Dr. Nadelmann also promoted the United States’ accession to the Rome International Institute for the Unification of Private Law (UNIDROIT) and the Hague Conference on Private Intemational Law23 where he was instrumental in drafting a judgments recognition convention.24 Regrettably,this effort failed for a number of reasons,25 and similar current endeavors may also come to naught because of the dismal state of American jurisdictional law.26 

The procedural part of the conflict of laws, jurisdiction and judgments recognition,is of great practical importance.My contribution to the Festschrift honoring Professor Yiannopoulos,however,will focus on choice of law.This field,though perhaps of lesser practical importance,is,in the eyes of many, much more befuddling than judgments recognition or even our strange jurisdictional lore.Not without reason,Dean Prosser characterized it as «a dismal swamp, filled with quaking quagmires» and complained about the «learned but eccentric [conflicts] professors who theorize about mysterious matters.»27 Certainly,few fields can boast of an equally «strange and incomprehensible jargon»28 as that which bedevils choice of law.No ordinary mortal,few lawyers and judges, and seemingly not even all conflicts teachers, truly understand such concepts as renvoi, characterization, dépeçage, and «rules of immediate application.»Quite apart from its cumbersome nomenclature, the field is mared by never-ending debates about the purposes it is to serve and the proper method to accomplish them. Accordingly, it is hardly surprising that confusion reigns supreme.Matters were bad enough when Prosser referred to our discipline as a «dismal swamp;» they have not improved since Joseph Beale’s spurious vested rights theory29 gave way to Brainerd Curmie’s equally spurious «govemmental interests»30 approach.Something called the «conflicts revolution» has swept the country and in its wake a peculiarly parochial attitude has spread.31 This parochialism is deplorable, because the field is desperately in need of the enlightenment comparison can offer.

II. Four Approaches

American conflicts law used to be a comparative endeavor. After losing Saul v. His Creditors,32 a landmark conflicts case,Samuel Livermore used the European literature he had consulted to persuade the Louisiana Supreme Court (to no avail) as material for the first American treatise on the subject.33 Justice Story, another comparativist,also looked to civilian sources to write his splendid Commentaries on the Conflict of Laws. a treatise that set new standards for the scholarly treatment of the subject.34 Although story did not embrace the statutist approach Livermore had advocated, he did pay homage to his predecessor.35 If it is true that the comparative method helped launch these two early treatises, might it not also be of assistance in the future? The turmoil that currently besets choice of law is due, at least in part, to the disregard of comparison and guidance from whatever source ought to be welcome.Indeed,comparative research has already revealed an important fact that might be pertinent to a much-needed reorientation of this field: In spite of its long history and the immense outpouring of scholarly writing and judicial opinions it has inspired, courts and legal writers have been able to come up with only a limited number of fundamental approaches to the multistate problems this area of the law is designed to resolve.36 This Article will briefly sketch the substance of these approaches.

A. Lex fori

Assume that a New York manufacturer sells widgets to a French buyer. What law should govem their agreement? One approach to this question is not to pose it at all. The court in which the transaction is litigated-be it in New York, France or some other state or nation-simply applies its own law. In support of this solution, it can be argued that judges are, after all, most familiar with the lex fori. Its application is therefore easier, less time-consuming, and (there being no need for a foreign law expert) cheaper than resort to the rules of decision of some alien legal system. By the same token, an erroneous application of the pertinent law will be less likely. That was indeed the way English common-law courts, after initially refusing even to hear cases involving foreign facts because the juries had to be drawn from the vicinage, used to deal with the problem some centuries ago. 37 Rather than simply dismissing such cases, the common-law courts resorted to the fiction that the foreign facts transpired in England, so that they could be tried before a jury and adjudicated by applying English law. 38 Of course, the English judiciary has long abandoned this rather extreme forum- centered approach. In fact, Parliament, following continental European practice, has recently gone as far as to enact statutory choice-of-law rules. 39 Yet, strange as it may seem, the rather archaic position that forum law should reign supreme has found favor with some American courts40 and contemporary American conflict of laws scholars. 41

B. Multilateralism

A different way to deal with the matter is the one followed by the first Restatement of Conflicts,42 which enshrined the so-called «multilateral approach, » a methodology propagated by Friedrich Carl von Savigny.43 To resolve contract choice-of-law issues, for instance, multilateralists ask «is this a French or a New York contract?» To answer this question, they interpose «jurisdiction-selecting rules»44 between the transaction and the legal systems whose laws potentially apply-rules that allocate the transaction to one legal system or the other by means of so-called «connecting factors. «45 Thus, the first conflicts restatement provided that the validity and effect of a contract are determined by the «law of the place of contracting. «46 The lex loci contractus was to govern practically all choice-of-law issues, save for certain ones relating to performance.47 This rather simplistic rule, which can be traced back to the Middle Ages,48 was believed to resolve, simply and expediently, any interstate or international contract problems that might conceivably arise. The purpose of such choice-of-law rules is, as Savigny49 pointed out, to provide for uniform results irrespective of where a case may be litigated.50 In other words, by striving for what civilians call «decisional harmony, «51 this approach attempts to eliminate the evil of forum shopping.

C. Unilateralism

While multilateralists attempt to allocate transactions to a particular legal system, unilateralists approach choice-of-law problems in a rather different manner. Instead of asking «is this a New York or a French contract?, » they look at the specific legal issues that have arisen and ask what rules of decision should govern each of them. For instance, if it is doubtful whether lack of consideration vitiates the parties’ agreement, unilateralists will ponder the possible reach of the pertinent local and foreign rules-whether they claim application to a contract that has contacts with the forum as well as with some other state. Thus, rather than locate a given legal transactions in one legal system or another, unilateralists inquire into the spatial purport of the potentially applicable domestic and foreign rules of decision, such as statutory provisions or case law rules on consideration, Again, the unilateralist methodology is not exactly new. Nine hundred years ago, scholars at Upper Italian universities attempted to divine the reach of rules of decision from their inherent characteristics.52 Thus, they speculated about whether a particular local rule on, for example, the capacity to contract, applies to a contract made by a nonresident in the forum or by a resident made abroad.53 Once considered outdated and worthless in light of Story’s and Savigny’s contributions to the conflict of laws,54 this approach was resuscitated in the United States by Brainerd Currie. who maintained that the policy behind each rule of decision and the interest of the state whose rule of decision is at issue in effectuating that policy, should determine the rule’s interstate or intermational scope.55

D. The Substantive Law Approach

A fourth way of dealing with the problem focuses on commonalities rather than on differences. Instead of determining whether a contract is French or New York in nature or whether the New York rule on consideration applies, the substantive law approach asks whether there is an interstate or intemational rule on point. This was the way in which Justice Joseph Story, the great conflicts scholar,56 dealt with an interstate negotiable instruments problem in Swift v. Tyson57 Justice Story’s opinion in Swifi eliminated the possible conflict between the asserted New York requirement of consideration and whatever rule may have prevailed in Maine, wherethe bill of exchange at bar was dated, by invoking a federal common-law rule derived from a supranational law merchant.58 As far as sales contracts are concemed, Justice Story’s approach has, in a way, become positive law:Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code largely eliminates conflicts within the United States. Intemationally, the Vienna Convention on the Law Applicable to International Sales of Goods,59 which the United States and most developed countries have ratified, lays down substantive rules governing the sale of merchandise across national boundaries, Thus, both within the United States and worldwide there now exists, once again, a uniform commercial law of sales.

Of course, American sales law is not entirely uniform because the versions of Article 2 enacted by ditferent states vary and the courts of each state may construe even identical provisions differently.60 As far as intemational sales are concerned, the modern lex mercatoria had to take the form of an international compact to become the supreme law of the land. 61 This is not what Justice Story had in mind when, in Swift v. Tyson, he talked about «the law. . . of the commercial world, «62 which is to say a supranational set of rules that is not the law of any particular state and does not owe its existence to treaties among nations. Rules of intermational commercial law do not necessarily require the exercise of sovereign prerogatives. The law merchant to which the great judge and conflicts scholar referred, the roots of which reach back to the Roman ius gentium. emerged from commercial custom during the Middle Ages, 63 when it helped Europe to escape from the Dark Ages that followed the fall of the Roman Empire.

This revival of Westem culture preceded the existence of territorial states and their claim to a monopoly in lawmaking. Once the world was divided into nation states, legal positivists, such as Justice Holmes, denied that such a supranational law could still exist. 64 But, while the United States Supreme Court has adopted Holmes’view, 65 a respectable array of current scholarly opinion maintains that modem realities, in particular the prevalence of arbitration as the means of resolving commercial disputes, have spawned a new law merchant. 66 Accordingly, the substantive law approach to multistate and multinational problems presents, even now, a possible altemative to the traditional multilateral and unilateral methodologies.

E. Eclecticism

These, then, are the four fundamental approaches to choice of law:(1) applying the lex fori. (2) multilateralism, (3) unilateralism, and (4) the substantive law approach. I say  «fundamental» because there are quite a few additional approaches, which will not appeal to purists, but seem to delight some legal scholars and courts. Taking a little bit of this, a little bit of that, and a tad of the other, scholars and judges have devised composites that they find more appealing than any plain vanilla choice-of-law methodology. There is, of course, nothing wrong with borrowing the best elements of various theories and combining them in some coherent fashion to create a new approach. The users and promoters of the various «mish-mash» or «kitchen sink» methodologies,67 however, tend to overlook that the four basic approaches reflect rather different ideologies and incompatible purposes, and therefore do not mix well. At any rate, for analytical purposes at least, it seems appropriate to keep the varying methodologies apart, even if it is true that no particular approach has ever prevailed, to the exclusion of all others, in the history of our discipline. 68

III. The Choice-of-Law Evolution

A. The Statutist Approach

Although the four methods outlined above have coexisted for centuries, their relative importance has varied over time. Since the Middle Ages, when continental European law teachers first began to wrestle with conflicts problems, the prestige of each method at any particular period has largely depended on the academic support it enjoyed. Early on, the statutists-who followed a unilateralist approach that classified rules of decision as either personal or territorial-dominated the field.69 Unilateralism, however, had to compete with the substantive law approach. Because of the Roman law revival in continental Europe, there reigned an overarching common law, a ius commune, which interacted with local law such as the statuta of the upper Italian city-states.70 Also, special commercial courts dealt with disputes among merchants, and these courts applied the lex mercatoria, a law of universal purport.71 Yet, although they were teachers of Roman law and presumably familiar with the law merchant, the statutists’ early conflicts literature was devoted primarily to the divination of the personal or territorial reach of rules of decision. Taking the existence of substantive norms governing multistate transactions for granted in dealing with the multistate transactions of their days, they emphasized the unilateral, rather than the multilateral or the substantive choice-of-law approaches,72 in dealing with the conflicts posed by disparate local laws.

B. The Emergence of Multilateralism

Subsequently, statutism became a discredited doctrine. As noted earlier, Samuel Livermore tried to import the statutist methodology to our shores, but Judge Porter of the Louisiana Supreme Court rebuffed Livermore’s effort and, in Saul v. His Creditors. opted for the multilateral methodology.73 «Justice Story(who had read the book that Livermore, atter having lost the Saul case, published on the subject)74 also rejected the statutist approach75 and promoted the development of multilateral choice-of-law rules.76 The eminent Roman law scholar Friedrich Carl von Savigny not only followed Story’s footsteps but, more importantly, fumished a conceptual foundation for multilateralism.77 » Given the reputation of Story’s Commentaries and Savigny’s treatise, it comes as no surprise that the switch they brought about from unilateralism to the multilateralist approach has been called a «Copemican revolution»78 Attributed to medieval minds and discredited by such extremes as Bartolus’s ludicrous attempt to deduce the spatial reach of rules of decision from their wording,79 statutism, and thus the unilateralist approach, may have looked moribund, if not dead. Instead of continuing to classify statutes as personal or real, scholars began to explore the ramifications of the multilateralist approach, especially its self-inflicted problems, such as characterization, public policy. and renvoi.80 But even during the heyday of what has been called the «classical» approach,81 unilateralism did not entirely vanish. It manifested itself, in particular, when courts had to deal with the application of regulatory laws, such as antitrust legislation, to international transactions.82 Moreover, swimming against the tide, even on the European Continent there were some academics who continued to find merit in the unilateralist creed.83

C. Unilateralism Redivivus

Ultimately, of course, it tumed out that the report of unilateralisı’s demise was greatly exaggerated. In a landmark article,a Belgian author described how that old approach managed to survive lean times84 and a Swiss jurist noted that «statutist theories… are experiencing a surprising renaissance.»85 Unlike in Europe and Latin America-where Savigny is still held in awe86 -in the United States unilateralism made a truly spectacular comeback,becoming the dominant school of thought.87 Brainerd Currie, who, echoing other eminent authors,88 debunked the multilateralist first conflicts Restatement and its Reporter Joseph Beale (as well as the entire multilateralist doctrine)89 and took the position that «[w]e would be better off without choice-of-law rules,»90 by which he meant those of the multilateralist kind. Hypothesizing state «terests» in applying Jomestic rules of decision to interstate and international transactions,91 he persuaded an entire generation of conflicts scholars that the only appropriate way to deal with choice-of-law problems is to focus on the spatial reach of substantive rules.

Currie’s articles,published in the late 1950s and early 1960s, had so powerful an impact on American conflict scholarship that the unilateralist revival was thought to be «Copernican revolution»92 To this day, Currie’s «interest analysis» claims center stage, and even those who reject it are forced to pay tribute to it by having to take issue with his postulates. A majority of American conflicts scholars probably still accepts his teachings, at least up to a point. As has been said:

Currie’s governmental interest analysis proved to be a water-shed in American conflicts law..[V]irtually every American conflicts scholar after 1958 took Currie’s analysis as a starting point either for agreement or disagreement. …No commentator on current develomen in American conflicts law even today can ignore Currie, for his scholars continue to debate his views even as they seek new ways yo approach the perennial problems of the subjet.93

While the views of current American interest analysts mat differ from Currie´sand often vary from one author to the next,94 their difference are, in large measure, limited to the question og how to deal whit the slef-inflicted problems of unilateralism – the so-called «true conflicts», «unprovided-for cases» an déécage.95 those who still cling to multilateralism in some form or other seem to do so less out of fondess for the traditional approach than out of the belief either that the Constitution comples rules that allocate «legislative juridistion» territorially96 or that a palliative is needed to alleviate unilateralism´s inherent forum bias.97

IV. Comparative Perspectives

A. The Pilfalls of Disdaining Comparison

However interesting the American conflicts revolution may be as a jurisprudential phenomenon, one might ask, what does it have to do with comparative law? The answer is: very little. In fact, the truly remarkable thing about the sea change in American conflicts law is the lack of reflection on the part of most revolutionaries. Authors such as David Cavers, Brainerd Currie, Willis Reese and others had little to say about the nature, background, and provenance of the methodologies they espoused. Although they were obviously aware of the marked difference between their approaches and the one underlying Beale’s First Restatement, they seemed to lack words to describe that difference, indeed, they may never have heard the terms unilateralism and «multilateralism». Only Albert Ehrenzweig, a comparativist, found it necessary to explain and define these concepts.98 But neither Currie nor his early followers, should they have read Ehrenzweig’s work, pondered their meaning and import, or even paid attention to them. Similar to Monsieur Jourdain in Molière’s play, who did not know that he had been speaking prose for forty years, they seemed to be blissfully unaware of the fact that the methodologies they embraced had names and historical antecedents. Might they have simply believed that their approaches accorded with the natural order of things?

That certainly seems to have been Currie’s view. Rejecting what he believed to be inferior European imports, he called for a «retum to methods that are indigenous to our legal system and that our judges and lawyers are fully competent to utilize. »99 Despite his parochial bent of mind, he sensed nevertheless that what he said could not be entirely novel;indeed he claimed to have diligently sought for evidence of its antiquity,100 But because he ignored what comparativists might have to offer by way of insights into conflicts history and methodology (when Currie cited Ehrenzweig’s writings or Rabel’s treatise,101  he usually did so only to take issue with these comparativists),102 Currie’s attempt to trace the origin of his ideas prompted him to misinterpret possibly pertinent authority. He cited a passage from Lord Kames’ Principles of Equity for the proposition that the reach of legal rules should be ascertained by means of some form of govemmental interest analysis.103 By chance, Currie had looked in the right place: In this earliest English-language contribution to our field, Lord Kames-a Scot and, therefore, a civilian-did discuss conflict-of-laws issues in statutist, hence unilateralist, terms.104 The passage from the first edition of Kames’Principles that Currie quotes, however, has nothing to do with choice-of-law methodology.105 Lead astray by his lack of comparative acumen, Currie misread the word prescription in that passage to connote a rule of decision, whereas Kames used this term in its civil-law meaning to denote a statute of limitations. As is apparent, disdain for comparative research has the propensity to lead scholars astray.

B. The Price of Parochialism

«Those who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat it. » 106 Their disregard of the comparative method prompted revolutionaries to reinvent the wheel. Long before Currie came across true conflicts107 and «unprovided-for cases, «108 earlier writers had discovered the conundrums of cumuls and lacunes the unilateralist methodology inevitably produces.109 Obviously, any approach that is geared to ascertaining the reach of domestic rules of decision is bound to create situations in which more states than one can claim to attach legal consequences to a particular transaction or in which no state can be said to make such a claim, Similarly, the basic idea in Baxter’s much-cited article on «comparative impairment»110 merely restates Pillet’s law of the least sacrifice.111 Cavers. having heard about Wachter from his comparativist colleague Nadelmann, who had translated passages from the nineteenth century author’s work,112 did notice that Wächter’s views have a singularly contemporary cast,113 although he failed to grasp what precisely the German unilateralist had in common with the American revolutionaries.114 

Even the revolutionaries’choice of topics demonstrates the perils of parochialism. Both Cavers and Currie had selected, for their supposedly seminal contributions to modern conflicts theory, a curiously dated problem, namely the choice-of-law ramifications of a married woman’s incapacity to contract.115 One wonders what prompted them to revisit the old Massachusetts case Milliken v. Pratt,116 considering that they wrote at a time when married women’s disabilities were no longer an issue. How can one explain that scholars bent on fashioning a brave new world of conflicts law would exhume such legal fossils to wrestle with a problem that, as Currie realized, was «small, trite, and not very practical?117 Lack of comparative acumen seems to have been the reason. Would they have chosen to ponder the conflicts implications of married women’s incapacities, had they known that the seventeenth-century author Benedict Carpzov had already dealt with it in unilateralist terms118 and that Wächter, writing in the nineteenth century, had advanced arguments quite similar to those presented by the modem revolutionaries to justify application of the lex fori?119 Having little use for comparative and historical research, Cavers and Currie even neglected to consult the reference to Story’s treatise in the Milliken case,120 which would have led them to discussions of married women’s disabilities by foreign authors whom Story cited and analyzed. A glance at legal history and comparative law might well have persuaded them to pick a more suitable subject for developing their «novel» approaches.

C. The Domestic Law Focus

The American unilateralists’ lack of interest in comparative research is not altogether surprising. For obvious reasons, their approaches-and in this respect Currie and Wächter are very much alike-are infused with a powerful forum bias.121 Those who try to gauge how far rules of decision reach tend to focus, first and foremost, on the reach of forum law, and that is also where their inquiry usually ends. Once the lex fori is believed to reign supreme, there is no longer any need to deal with foreign law;parochialism becomes the name of the game. Under Currie’s spell, American conflicts law lost the cosmopolitan quality with which Livermore’s and Story’s comparative research had endowed122 it and which even the often maligned Beale respected.123 Of the four principal pre-revolutionary scholars who initially attacked Beale’s simplistic approach,124 Iwo had still been comparativists.125 But once Currie’s ideology commanded the center stage of the revolution, much of American conflicts literature began to take on a distinctive ethnocentric hue. To be sure, two distinguished comparativists, Albert Ehrenzweig and Arthur von Mehren, were among the revolutionaries. As important as their contributions are, however, they were marginalized by the tendency of American conflicts authors to focus on Currie’s teachings, be it to proclaim their allegiance or to take issue with him.

The substantive issues discussed in our conflicts literature also have a pronounced domestic character because American cours used the revolutionary approaches primarily to deal with interstate phenomena such as automobile accidents126 and airplane crashes127 Even events occurring beyond the American frontiers often posed issues resembling those presented in purely domestic cases.128 Combined with the forum bias of interest analysis, this resemblance may explain why courts failed to question whether the policies behind alien rules of decision were in fact identical to those underlying similar domestic rules. For example, a Califomia Supreme Court decision dealing with a cap on tort liability found in the Zacatecas Civil Code relied on Cavers’ discussion of American wrongful death statutes129 as authority to divine the policy that the Zacatecan legislature might have had in mind.130 Neither Zacatecas nor any other Mexican state, however, had ever faced the problem posed by Baker v. Bolton,131 in reaction to which common-law jurisdictions adopted their peculiar wrongful death acts, and Cavers had expressly disavowed any expertise in comparative law.132   Similarly, the New York Court of Appeals relied on an article by Reese, who had never claimed to be a Canadian law expert. to ascertain Ontario’s policy behind that Province’s guest statute.133 Not only did American courts cite spurious authority for asserted foreign policies, but at times they altogether avoided discussing policies other than domestic ones, as demonstrated by a spectacular Califomia federal case dealing with an air crash in France that killed people from five continents.134

Thus, in various and sundry ways the revolutionary case law failed to raise foreign-law problems in a manner that would necessitate recourse to the comparative method. Instead, it dealt primarily with dated domestic institutions that are of marginal interest to comparativists, such as guest statutes, intra-family immunity and caps on wrongful death recovery135 At the same time, conflicts commentators emphasized interstate rather than intemational conflicts, Moreover, as noted earlier, Currie had called for the retum to indigenous methodologies and found it unnecessary to look beyond domestic law for enlightenment.136 In this fashion, a number of factors combined to give the conflict of laws a strangely ethnocentric quality. Twenty-five years ago, an eminent German conflicts scholar already conciuded that American authors are stewing in their own juice.137 This is a serious matter. In consequence of our self-imposed insularity, we are in danger of losing touch with the rest of the world. Nor does such insular conflicts scholarship particularly please the judiciary. The theoretical refinements American scholars developed in splendid isolation are not especially helpful in deciding interstate and international cases; in fact, it seems that the judges do not even take them seriously.138

D. The Effect of «Globulization»

The fact that our discipline has been preoccupied with domestic phenomena ought to be of some concem to law teachers now that globalization has become the cliché of choice and acronyms such as EU, NAFTA, and WTO are bantered about daily by the media, Is it not strange to see scholars who work in a field that is dedicated to phenomena that transcend local boundaries glorify the lex fori? Attomeys who advise clients on international transactions must wonder how an area of law that ought to facilitate such transactions could produce homespun forum-centered approaches. Scholars who are preoccupied with sovereign prerogatives and focus on domestic courts and local laws fail to take into account the ease with which players on the international stage can avoid national courts and dysfunctional domestic precepts by recourse to arbitration. This preferred method of dispute resolution allws private parties to frustrate the governmental interests that supposedly control multistate transactions. In surroundings that display neither national flags nor other emblems, these interests are obviously of lesser concern than they would be in a courthouse. Because arbitrators are not beholden to the laws of any particular nation, arbitration effectively denationalizes intemational commercial disputes, eradicating the fixed point in the interest analysts universe; because there is no forum, forum interests become irrelevant.

And what law do such nonnational tribunals apply? Above all, they apply that law which the parties tell them to apply. Traditionalists, be they of the unilateral or the multilateral ilk, have never felt entirely comfortable with the power of individuals and enterprises to stipulate the law governing their contracts, because such a pragmatic solution is at odds with either of the two traditional approaches.139 Obviously. unilateralists who emphasize the notion of sovereignty will deny that there is any room in conflicts law for the interests of individuals or enterprises.140 But multilateralists as well have questioned the power of private parties to designate the applicable law,141 despite the fact that private parties could always manipulate even such seemingly hard-and-fast connecting factors as the place of contracting or performance. But, whatever scruples scholars may have, arbitrators-who, after all, owe their jobs to the parties who appointed them-will hardly question the wisdom of these parties’ choice. Even if arbitral tribunals, like courts, would have to respect choice-of-law rules,142 the fundamental principle of party autonomy is by now firmly rooted in domestic legislation and international conventions.143

As far as intermationalizing commercial transactions is concerned, much has been written about the new law merchant.144 This phenomenon has been prompted by the emergence of arbitration as the preferred method of commercial dispute resolution and the realization of inherent deficiencies in the conflict-of-laws approach to international transactions. Recourse by arbitrators to a nonnational lex mercatoria seems entirely appropriate if the parties fail to stipulate the law they wish to govern. Absent a foruim, the selection of the applicable law should not hinge on any positive choice-of-law rules. But even if it did, modem contract choice-of-law rules, which rely on such nebulous connecting factors as the «closest connection»145 or the «most significant relationship»,146 allow arbitrators to determine the law they wish to govem first and then to find reasons why that particular law has the closest connection with the parties’ agreement. Given such freedom, why should arbitrators be precluded from selecting a nonnational law, such as the UNIDROIT Principles of Intemational Commercial Contracts?147 In fact, there are reported cases to show that some arbitral tribunals preferred, even before the Principles-which are the result of one of the most important comparative endeavors ever undertaken-were published, an amorphous lex mercatoria to the positive law of some state or nation,148 Nor is arbitration the only driving force behind the quest for a supranational law of commerce:Standard form contracts and commercial customs contribute t the formation of a new law merchant149 akin to the old one of which Justice Story spoke in Swift v. Tyson.150

V. The Importance of Comparison

The most striking feature of the American conflicts revolution has been the shift from the multilateralist to the unilateralist methodology, which not only continues to occupy scholars in the United States, but has also had reverberations abroad. Even in countries where multilateralism is firmly established, authors are aware of such specific manifestations of the unilateralist methodology as rules of immediate application(lois de police) and the clash of regulatory laws.151 In fact, as mentioned earlier, perceptive civilian commentators have noted the remarkable resurgence of a method that had long been considered outdated.152 But the upheaval in the American conflict of laws did not merely revive the unilateralist methodology. Although most conflicts scholars in this country are still grappling with the ramifications of Currie’s methodology, a few would resuscitate multilateralism153 and some favor an unabashed leggeforismo.154 At the same time, the substantive law approach has reappeared, both on the international scene in the form of the much debated lex mercatoria155 and in domestic discussion as the better-law methodology156 That approach merits further exploration precisely because it is at loggerheads with fundamental tenets held dear by traditionalists. It contradicts the assumption of positivists, be they of the unilateralist or the multilateralist creed, that states, and only states, can create law.157

A. A Neglected Subject

While a hundred flowers bloom at home, many American conflicts writers have failed to pay attention to what is going on in international commercial practice. Thus, most of those who attended the symposium on the emerging lex mercatoria held at Tulane University ten years ago were not conflicts specialists, nor have American conflicts scholars published much since about this remarkable phenomenon, in spite of the rich literature on point.158 Such neglect, as noted elsewhere, comes close to educational malpractice.159 After all, the students we teach today are bound to encounter the new law merchant in practice. The failure to discuss an emerging trend of considerable practical importance further impoverishes American conflicts teaching, which has already ceded much ground to courses on intemational business transactions. More importantly、 conflicts teachers should not pass up the opportunity presented by this novel phenomenon to test the validity of firmly held beliefs about the proper approach to multistate problems. The neglect of the new law merchant and the better-law methodology is especially puzzling because they pose such fundamental questions as whether the contlict of laws ought to be unconcerned about substantive values and whether our discipline can render contributions to the harmonization of the laws goveming multistate transactions, Surely, these questions are more challenging than the purely inner-national problems with which American conflicts scholarship has been preoccupied for so long

B. The Role of State Courts

There are, however, some reasons for optimism. First of all, in marked contrast to its interventionist stance in the law of jurisdiction, the Supreme Court has fortunately not seen fit to intervene much in the field of choice of law. Instead of laying down principles, or even guidelines, it has merely established vague minimum requirements concerning the links a transaction must have with the forum to justify application of its law.160 As the Supreme Court put it, there must be a ‘significant contact or significant aggregation of contacts’ . . . ‘creating state interests, ‘ . . . to ensure that the choice of. . 。[forum law is not arbitrary or unfair.161 This loose verbiage, which ostensibly validates Currie’s governmental interest approach, in effect amounts to the recognition of a states’rights charter162 that leaves state judiciaries free to experiment. Because of the minimum contacts requirement for judicial jurisdiction,163 a court will rarely lack the necessary «significant contacts».164 Once it has such contacts, they will apparently spawn the interests the Supreme Court requires for what has been called «jurisdiction to prescribe».165 It is then up to the forum to apply any law that is somehow linked to the dispute at hand. In practice, state courts have quite frequently availed themselves of this freedom to reach fair results in conflicts cases.166 If the outcomes of reported decisions are any indication, judges. unlike most scholars, seem to share the opinion that the quality of legal rules and the results they produce do matter.167 Specifically, a review of the American case law dealing with multistate traffic accidents and products liability-the main battlefields of the conflicts revolution-shows that the position of interstate accident victims has improved considerably.168 This improvement is due in pant to the current methodologies’ homing trend. Whereas current unilateralist methodologies purport to vindicate sovereign concerms, in practical application their built-in forum bias allovs tort plaintiffs to liberate themselves from noxious rules by means of forum shopping. Exploiting the homing trend of interest analysis, counsel in effect subvert the very interests that Currie thought were all-important. In this fashion, the modem approaches tend to produce acceptable solutions in multistate tort cases.169 In contracts litigation, on the other hand, judges, in disregard of scholarly objections,170 vindicate substantive concems by following the worldwide trend honoring the parties’ autonomy to select the applicable law.171 Thus, in practice, if not in theory, American courts reach results that can be more readily explained by the substantive law approach than by orthodox methodologies.

C. A Word in Conclusion

The disparity between conflicts theories and actual decisions in multistate cases might suggest that, notwithstanding certain defects in academic methodologies, things are actually in pretty good shape, because courts do, on the whole, reach fair decisions in interstate and intemational cases. But the currently fashionable choice-of-law approaches do not necessarily enable judges to reach palatable results. While the effect of conflicts ideologies on the adjudication of multistate cases may not be all that great,172 judicial instinct does not invariably overcome the defects of a dubious methodology, as more than one decided case demonstrates.173 And, of course, the discrepancy between doctrine and judicial practice hardly presents a reason for rejoicing. But even in the academic realm, there is a ray of hope. The standard casebook that most prominently promotes govemmental interest analysis now devotes some space to intermational problems174 and two recent ones emphasize the intemational and comparative approach in their titles.175 

Last year, the author of one of them served as the General Reporter on Private International Law at the Xth International Congress of Comparative Law.176 A helpful introduction to foreign conflicts thinking and practice that appeared a few years ago should facilitate comparative research.177 Thus there is hope that American conflicts scholarship will escape its introspective phase, that the discrepancy between theory and practice will be overcome, and that there will be a greater «interest in a comparative study of basic assumptions held by traditional choice-of-law theories».178 As we approach the end of this millennium, we may well witness a retum to the comparative law tradition that used to be the hallmark of American conflicts law.

Bibliografía Sumaria

*Edward L. BARRETT, Jr., Professor of L.aw, University of California at Davis

  1. See Joseph STORY, Commentaries on the Conflict of Laws 11(2d. ed. 1841)».
  2. [C]omparative law is enormously valuable for private international law, indeed so indispensable for its development that the methods of private intermational law today are essentially those of comparative law». Konrad ZWEIGERT&Hein KoTz, Introduction to Comparative Law 6 (Tony Weir trans, 3d ed 1998)
    [T]he theory and practice of private international law are inexorably involved with comparative law and the comparative method whenever the rules and institutions of a legal system other than the torum’s must be taken into account.
    [N]o system or private international law can lotally escape involvement with the discipline of comparative law. To the extent that a forum applies foreign law, the foreign-law dimension of the comparative discipline is relevant, although only on an ad hoc basis.
    Arthur TAYLOR von MEHREN The Contribution of Comparative Law to the Theory and Practice of Privale International Lawin Law in the U. S. A. in the Bicentennial Era, 26 Am, J. Comp. L. (Supp. ) 31. 32-33 (1978)[hereinatter von Mehren, Theory and Practice].
  3. ZWEIGERT &KOTZ, supra note 2, at 15
    [T]he method of comparative law can provide a much richer range of model solutions than a legal science devoted to a single nation, simply because the diflerent systems of the world can ofler a greater variety of solutions than could be thought up in a lifetime by even the most imaginative jurist who was corralled in his own system. Comparative law is an ‘école de verité’ which extends and enriches the supply of solutions’ and olfers the scholar of critical capacity the opportunity of finding the ‘hetter solution’ for his time and place Id. .
  4. See Friedrich K. JUENGER, American Jurisdiction Story of Comparative Neglect, 65 U. Colo. L. Rev. l (1993) [hereinafter Juenger, American Jurisdiction].
  5. See Convention on Jurisdiction and Enforcement of Judgments in Civil and Commercial Matters, Sept 27. 1968, 1968 O. J. (1. 299) 1. as amended, 1990 J. O (C 189) 1, reprinted in 29 1. L M. 1413 (1990).
  6. See Convention on Jurisdiction and Enforcement of Judgments in Civil and Commercial Matters, Sept. 16. 1988. 1988 0J. (L 319) 9, reprinted in 28 I. L M. 620(1989).
  7. See JUENGER, American Jurisdiction, supra note 4, at 6, 10.
  8. See id. .
  9. Fed R. Civ. P. I. .
  10. See JUENGER. American, hurisdiction supra note 4 at 3. .
  11. See id at 21-22.
  12. See Friedrich K. JUENGER. The Recognition of Money Judgmenis in Civil and Commercial Matters, 36 Am. J. Comp. L. 1, 9-10(1988).
  13. See id. at 5-6.
  14. See id. at 6-7. .
  15. See id. at 7-8, 31-34.
  16. See id. at 29-31.
  17. See id. 31 34.
  18. 159U. S. 113, 227-28 (1895). .
  19. See Eugene F. ScoLEs&Peter HAY, Conflict of Laws 999, 1003(2d ed, 1992). .
  20. See David F. CAVERS Kurt Hans NADELMANN, Foreword to Kunt H. NADELMANN, Conflict of Laws:Intemational and interstate al xi, xv(1972)hereinalter CAVERS, Nadelmann);Arthur T. von MEHREN, The Writings of Kurt H Nadelmann. Introductory Essay to Nadelmann, supra, at xvii, xxii, .
  21. See Unit Foreign Money Judgments Recognition Act, 13 U. L. A. 261(1986).
  22. For a list of adoptions, see 13 UL A 80(Supp. 1998).
  23. See CAVERS. Nadelmann supra note 20, at xv. von Mehren, supra note 20, at xx-xi.
  24. See Convention on the Recognition and Enforcement of Judgments in Civil and Commercial Matters, Feb 1, 1971, 1144 U. N T. S. 249, von Mehren, supra note 20. at xxii. .
  25. See Friedrich K. JUENGER, A Hague Judgmenis Convention?, 24 Brook. J. INT’L. L. 111. 112(1998).
  26. See id. at 117-20 .
  27. William L. Prosser, Interstate Publicution, 51 Mich. L. Rev. 959, 971(1953).
  28. Id. .
  29. See 1 Joseph H. BEALE, A Treatise on the Conflict of Laws 53(1935), Friedrich K. JUENGER. Choice of Law and Multistate Justice 90-91 (1993) hereinafter JUENGER, Multistate Justice), see also 3 Beale, supra, at 1967-69.
  30. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 98-103.
  31. See id at 92-128.
  32. 5 Man (n. s. ) 569 (La. 1827). .
  33. See Samuel LIVERMORE, Dissertations on the Questions Which Arise from the Contrariety of the Posilive Laws of Different States and Nations (1828) NADELMANN, supra note 20, at 7-8.
  34. See JuENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29 at 29-31 (discussing Story, supra note 1).
  35. See STORY, supra note 1, at 13 n 3. see also NADELMANN, supra note 20, at 10, 34 (explaining that Story had benefited because Livenmore had left his library to Hlarvard, thus expanding the foreign literature Story could consuit).
  36. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 45-46. .
  37. See Alexander N. SAcK, Conflicis of Laws in the History of the English Law, in 3 l. aw A Century of Progress 342, 344-46(1937).
  38. See id at 370-71.
  39. See Conflict of Laws Act, 1995, ch 42(Eng).
  40. See, eg, Adams v. J. B Hunt Transp, Inc. , 130 F. 3d 219, 230-31 (6th Cir, 1997) (primacy of forum law); Sutherland v Kennington Truck Serv. , Ltd. , 562 N. W 2d 466, 471(Mich 1997)(same).
  41. See infra note 154 and accompanying text. .
  42. See Restatement of Contlict of Laws(1934).
  43. See 8 Friedrich KARL Von SAVIGNY, System des Heutigen Römischen Rechts (1849), see also JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 34-40.
  44. See David F. CAVERS, The Choice-of-law Process 9 n. 24(1965)[hereinafter CAVERS, Process]. .
  45. See id. at 65.
  46. Restatement, supra note 42, 332. .
  47. See id  358.
  48. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 13.
  49. Savigny himself, however, advocated the place-of-pertormance rule and party autonomy rather than the lex loci contractus, See SAVIGNY, supra note 43, at 203-15, 246-49, 256-57. .
  50. See id at 128-29.
  51. See. e. g, Jan KROPHOLLER, Intemationales Privatrecht 35 (3d ed. 1997)(Enischeidungsharmonie)Picrre MAYER, Droit International Prive 56(5th ed. 1994)(hurmonie des solutions). .
  52. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 12-13.
  53. See id at 13. .
  54. See infra notes 78-79 and accompanying text.
  55. Currie’s ideas are contained in a series of articles, most of which were reprinted in Brainerd Currie, Selected Essays on the Conflict of Laws(1963)hereinafter CURRIE, Conflict of Laws.
  56. For a brief discussion of Justice Story’s contribution to the conflict of laws, see JUENGER, Multistate Justice. supra note 29, at 29-31.
  57. 41 1U S. (16 Pet. )1(1842). ovemuled by Erie R. R v. Tompkins, 304 U. S. 64, 79(1938).
  58. See id al 18-22.
  59. See United Nations Convention on Contracts for the Iniernational Sale of Goods Final Act. U. N. Doc NCONF 97/18(1980), reprinted in S. Treaty Doc. No. 98-9, 98th Cong, Ist Sess. , app. B (1980), and in 191L. M 668(1980).
  60. And, of course, Louisiana has never enacted Article 2 of the UCC (although its law has been influenced by that Article).
  61. See U. S. Const. art. VI, cl. 2.
  62. 41 U. S (16 Pet. ) at 19. .
  63. See Harold J. BERMAN, Law and Revolution The Formation of the Westem Legal Tradition 333-56(1983), Leon E. TRAKMAN, The Law Merchant:the Evolution of Commercial Law 7-21 (1983).
  64. See Black&White Taxicah&Transter Co. v. Brown&Yellow Taxicab& Transter Co. , 276 U. S. 518, 533 (1928)(Holmes, J. , dissenting).
  65. See Erie R. R. v Tompkins, 304 U S. 64. 79 (1938) (quoting portions of Holmes’s dissenting opinion in Black & White Taxicab 276 US at 533).
  66. See, eg. TRAKMAN, supra note 63, at 97-105; Harold J. Berman&Felix J. Dasser, The New Law Merchant and the Old:Sources, Conlent, and Legitimacy, in Lex Mercatoria and Arbitration 53 (Thomas E. Carbonneau ed, rev. ed. 1998) 67.
  67. These methodologies were aptly so named by William A Reppy, Jr. , Eclecticism in Choice of Law: Hybrid Method or Mishmash?, 34 Mercer L Rev. 645, 653(1983).
  68. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 140.
  69. See id at 14-15.
  70. See eg. Helmut Coing, The Roman Law as lus Commune on the Continent. 89 LQ. REV. 505 (1973). Reinhard Zimmermann, Roman-Dutch Jurisprudence and lis Contribution to European Privale Law. 66 Tul L Rev. 1685(1992).
  71. See supra note 63 and accompanying text.
  72. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 11-13. .
  73. See supra notes 32-35 and accompanying text.
  74. See STORY, supra note 1, at 13 n 3.
  75. See id. at 13-24.
  76. See, eg. id at 173 (lex loci celebrationis), id at 319 (lex loci contractus), id. at 609 (lex rei sitae).
  77. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, al 39-40.
  78. See Paul HEINRICH NEUHAUS, Diegrundbegriffe des Internationalen Privatrechts 94(2d ed, 1976).
  79. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra nole 29, at 14.
  80. See id. at 70-81.
  81. See id at 47.
  82. See. eg, Schoenbaum v. Firstbrook, 405 F 2d 200, 206-09(2d Cir. 1968) (involving U S, securities regulation law), United States v. Aluminum Co of Am. , 148 F 2d 416, 444 (2d Cir. 1945)(involving U S antitrust laws). William S. Dodge, Extraterritorialiy and Conjlict-of-Laws Theorv In Argument for Judicial Unilaleralism, 39 HARV. INT’L LJ, 101, 106-10, 123-27(1998).
  83. See, e. g. Antoine Pillet, Théorie Continentale des Connits de Lois, in 2 Collccted Courses of the Hague Academy of Comparative Law 451, 469-70(1924), Giuseppe Sperduti, Théorie du Droit International Privé, in 122 Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of Comparative Law 173, 178-84, 190, 320-21(1967) Seegenerally Rudolf WIETHOLTER, Einseitige Kollisionsnormen als Grundlage des Internationalen Privatrechts(1956). .
  84. See PierregoTHOT, Le Renouveau de la Tendance Unilateraliste en Droit International Prive (pts. 1-3), 60 Revue Critique de Droit Intemational Privé 1, 209, 415 (1971).
  85. Frank VISCHER, Das Neue Restatement Conflict of Laws 38 Rabels Zeitschrift 128. 137(1974), see also Erik JAYME, Identile Culiurelle er Inlégration Le Droit International Privé Postmoderne, in 251 Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law 9, 91-93(1995)(discussing the renaissance of statutist theory). .
  86. See eg, MAYER, supra note 51, at 54-55;P. M. North&J. J Fawcett, Cheshire and North’s Private International Law 23(12th ed 1992), Haroldo TEXEIRO VALLADAO, Derecho Intemacional Privado 58-59 (Leonel Pereznieto Castro trans. , 1987).
  87. See Herma HiL KAY, A Defense of Currie’s Governmental Interest Analysis, in 215 Collected Courses of The Hague Academy of International Law 9, 78, 198(1989).
  88. See. e. g. David F. CavERs, A Critique of the Choice-of-Law Problem, 47 HARV. L REV. 173(1933) [hereinafter Cavers, A Critique], Waller WHEELER Cook, The Logical and Legal Bases of the Conhict of Laws, 33 Yale I. J 457(1924).
  89. See CURRIE. Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, passim.
  90. Id at 183.
  91. See, eg, id. at 53, 89, 94. 112. .
  92. See Arthur TAYLOR von MEHREN, Recent Trends in Choice-of-Law Methodology. 60 Comell L Rev. 927, 933(1975). .
  93. KAY, supra note 87, at 78.
  94. See id at 179-82.
  95. For a discussion of these conundrums and the reasons for their existence, see JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra ote 29, at 138-39.
  96. See Douglas LAYcock. Equal Citizens of Equal and Territorial States The Constitunional Foundations of Choice of Law, 92 Colum L. Rev. 249. 315-36(1992)(suggesting that choice-of-law rules should be derived from constitutional principles) But see Perry Dane, Vested Righis Festednessand Choice of Law. 96 Yale LJ. 1191, 1242-72(1987) (defending multilateralism), Alfred HILL, The Judicial Function in Choice of Law. 85 Colum L Rev. 1585, 1619-23(1985) (arguing that traditional choice-of-law rules continue to have precedential value).
  97. See. eg, Larry KRAMER, Rethinking Choice of Law, 90 Colum L Rev. 277. 311-44(1990). Arthur | von MEHREN, Choice of Law and the Problem of Jusrice. 41 Law & Contemp. Probs. 27. 34(1977).
  98. Ehrenzweig called these concepts ‘unilateral’ and ‘universal’ conflicts rules Albert A. Ehrenzweig. A Treatise on the Conflict of Laws 312-13(1962). .
  99. CURRIE, Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, at 627. .
  100. Id. at 612. .
  101. See Emst RABEL. The Conflict of Laws. A Comparative Study(2d ed. 1958).
  102. See CURRIE. Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, at 476-77, 580 n 213, 700 n, 34, 725 n. 118. 742 n 155 (disparaging Ehrenzweig’s views). id. at 433-34, 709-10 (disputing Rabel’s views).
  103. See Henry HOME KAMES, Principles of Equity 188. 283, 379, 612(1760).
  104. See Henry HOME KAMES, Principles of Equity 345-74 (2d ed 1767).
  105. See CURRIE, Conflict of Laws, supra nole 55, at 188. .
  106. George SANTAYANA, The Life of Reason or the Phases of Human Progress 284(1905).
  107. The thommy problem of cumuls, which results if the laws of two or more states vie for applications has given interest analysts much grief, See, e. g. . Roger C. CRAMTON et al, Conflict of Laws 175-202 (5th ed 1993) Symeon C Symeonides er al, Conflict of Laws: American. Comparative, International 120-21. 179-224(1998).
  108. Currie saw the problem (he called it the unprovided case), but did not worry much about it See CURRIE. Contlict of Laws, supra note 55, at 152-53 He opined that traditionalists may stand aghast at this anomaly, hut reminded them that the traditional conflict of laws system may produce similar lacuna. ld. at 152-53. His use of this tenm, of whose civilian origin he seemed to be unaware, illustrates Currie’s propensity to reinvent the wheel. .
  109. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 138.
  110. See William F. BAXTER Choice of Law and the Federal Svstem, 16 STAN, L. REV. 1(1963). .
  111. See PILLET, supra note 83, at 472.
  112. See Kurt H. NADELMANN, Wachier’s Essay on the Collision of Private Laws of DifTerent States, 13 Am J. Comp. L. 414(1964).
  113. CAVERS, Process, supra note 44, al 4. .
  114. See id at 4 n. 7.
  115. See CAVERS, A Crilique, supra note 88, at 180, Brainerd Currie, Married Women’s Contracts. A Study in Connici-of-Laws Method, 25 U. CHI. L. REV. 227(1958).
  116. 125 Mass, 374(1878).
  117. CURRIE, Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, at 107.
  118. See Max GUTZWILLER Geschichte des Intemationalprivatrechts 182 (1977), Günter Merzyn, Der Beitrag Benedikt Carpzovs Zur Entwicklung des Kollisionsrechts 17-18 (1963) Like CAVERS, 4 Crilique, supra note 88, at 180, 189-90, and CURRIE, Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, at 85-86, Carpzov pondered whether a forum state that limits a married woman’s capacity can deny a foreign woman the capacity she enjoys pursuant to the law of her home state. See MERZYN, supra, at 17. He concluded, however, that the torum has the power to do so to effectuate its protective policy, and that, conversely, the forum slate can emancipate toreign women whose home-state law incapacitates them. See id at 17-18. As can be seen, the unilateralism or yore had the same forum bias as that of today. The results that Carpzov reached should certainly have been congenial to Currie, even though he would not havegiven the benetit of a protective forum law to a foreign emancipated women See CURRIE, Contlict of Laws, supra nole 55, at 111-19 But would Curmie have been pleased about someone engaging in the same exercise and anticipaling his thought processes by three centuries? It so, would Currie have felt it necessary to squander time on thoroughly dated stuff?.
  119. See Wachter, Ueber die Collision der Privatrechtsgesetze verschiedener Staaten (pt. 3), 24 Archiv tur die civilistische praxis 161, 180(1842).
  120. See MILLIKEN. 125 Mass. at 381. .
  121. See JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 33-34. .
  122. See supra notes 32-35 and accompanying text 12).
  123. See 3 BEALE, supra note 29, at 1880-1975, for a thoughtful analysis of the history of the conflict of laws and the work of foreign conflicts authors Beale also translated Bantolus’s lamous tract See Bantolus on the Contlict of laws (Joseph H Beale trans, 1914).
  124. Concerning the pre-revolutionary scholars David F. CAVERS, Walter WHEEL. ER Cook, Ernest G. LOREN ZEN and Hessel E. YNTEMA, see JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 92.
  125. See, eg. Emest G. LORENZEN, Territoriality, Public Policy and the Confict of Laws, 33 Yale L. J. 736 (1924), Hessel E YNTEMA, The Comity Doctrine, 65 MICH. L. REV. 9(1966).
  126. See. eg. Reich v. Purcell, 432 P. 2d 727(Cal. 1967), Tooker v. Lopez, 249 N. E. 2d 394(N. Y. 1969).
  127. See, eg. Pearson v. Northeast Airlines, Inc. 309 F. 2d 553(2d Cir. 1962), Griffith v. United Air Lines. Inc, 203 A. 2d 796(Pa 1964).
  128. See eg, Hurtado v. Superior Court, 522 P 2d 666 (Cal. 1974)(regarding the applicability of Mexico’s statutory ceiling to a wrongful death case on recovery). Babcock v. Jackson. 191 N. E. 2d 279 (N. Y. 1963)(involving the applicability of Ontario’s guest statutc in New York).
  129. See CAVERS, Nadelmann, supra note 20, at 103, cited in HURTADO, 522 P, 2d at 670, .
  130. See HURTADO. 522 P. 2d at 670.
  131. 170 Eng. Rep. 1033(K B. 1808).
  132. See David F CAVERS, Contemporarv Conflicis Law in American Perspective, in 131 Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of Intemational Law 75. 86(1970).
  133. See Neumeier v. KUEHNER, 286 N E. 2d 454, 455(N. Y. 1972) (citing Willis L M. Reese, Chief Judge Fuld and Choice of Law, 71 Colum. L. Rev, 548. 558(1971)).
  134. See In re Paris Air Crash of March 3, 1974, 399 F Supp. 732(C. D. Cal. 1975).
  135. Landmark decisions that to this day feature prominently in the casebooks include Reich v. Purcell, 432 P. 2d 727 (Cal. 1967) (involving a cap on wrongful death recovery), Wartell v. Formusa, 213 N. E, 2d 544 (111. 1966)(regarding interspousal immunity), and Babcock v. Jackson, 191 N. E 2d 279 (N. Y. 1963)(concerning a guest stalute).
  136. See supra note 99 and accompanying text. .
  137. "[K]ochen im eigenen Safi Gerhard Kegel Wandel aufdünnem Eis, in Friedrich K. JUENGER, Zum WAN. DEL DES INTERNATIONALEN PRIVATRECHTS 35. 41 (1974). see also von MEHREN, Theory and Practice. supra note 2, at 39-40.
  138. See Patrick J, BORCHERS, The Choice-of-Law Revolution An Empirical Snudy. 49 Wash. &Lee L. Rev. 357, 379(1992), Stewant E STERK, The Marginal Relevance of Choice of Law Theory, 142 U Pa. L. Rev. 949, 951, 1031(1994).
  139. See. eg, 2 BEALE, supra note 29, at 1079-83;CURRIE Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, al 103, Joseph William SINGER, Real ConAicts, 69 B UI, L. REV. 1, 75-76(1989).
  140. See CURRIE, Conflict of Laws, supra note 55, at 610.
  141. See, eg. Quintin ALFONSIN, Régimen Intemacional de los Contratos 13-27 (1950). 2 BEALE. supra note 29. al 1079-83.
  142. That indeed is the position taken by thegerman legislature, which has ordained that, in arbitrations governed by German law, the arbitrators are bound by thegerman conflict-of-laws rules. See § 1051 2 ZPO. .
  143. See, eg, Introductory Act to thegerman Civil Code (EGBGB) art 27(1), European Convention of 19 Juune 1980 on the Law Applicable to Contractual Obligations, art. 3(1), 1980 O. J, (L 266) 1, reprinted in 19 I. L. M. 1492(1980)hereinafter Rome Convention).
  144. See eg, Lex Mercatoria, supra note 66 Friednich K JUENGER, American Conflicis Scholarship and the New Law Merchant, 28 Vand: J Transnatl L. 487 (1995) (noting further references) (hereinafter Juenger. Neu Law Merchant].
  145. See Rome Convention, supra note 143, art. 4(1).
  146. See Restatement (second) of Contlict of Laws § 187(2)(1971).
  147. 34 I L. M. 1067(1995)seegenerally Michael Joachim Bonell, An Intemational Restatement of Contract Law(2d ed. 1997).
  148. See. e. g. Compania Valenciana, Cass le Civ. , 1991 Bull Civ I. No. 1345; Norsolor, S. A. v. Palbalk Ticaret Ltd, 1984 Y B. Comm. Arb. 161 (Aus ). Seegenerallv Filip de Ly, International Business Law and Lex Mercatoria 254-66(1992).
  149. See De Lv, supra note 148. at 133-205.
  150. 41 U. S. (16 Pet. )1(1842), overruled by Erie R. R v. Tompkins, 304 U. S. 64. 79(1938).
  151. See. eg. , KROPHOLLER, supra note 51, at 94-95, MAYER, supra note 51, at 88-95 (noting further references).
  152. See supra notes 84-87 and accompanying text.
  153. See DANE, supra note 96, Laycock, supra note 96.
  154. See STANLEY E. Cox, Razing Connicis Facades to Build Belter Jurisdiction Theory The FoundationThere is No Law But Forum Law, 28 Val. U. L. Rev. 1(1993), Harold G. MAIER&Thomas R. McCOY, 4 Unifying T’heory for Judicial Jurisdiction and Choice of Law, 39 AM. J. Comp. L. 249(1991).
  155. See supra notes 144-149 and accompanying text.
  156. See. eg, JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 233-37;Robert A. LEFLAR eI al, American Conflicts Law 14, 297-300(4th ed. 1986).
  157. See supra notes 64-65 and accompanying text. .
  158. See the bibliography in De Ly, supra note 148, at 323-57.
  159. See JUENGER, New Law Merchant supra note 144. at 500-01.
  160. See Phillips Petroleum Co. v, Shutts, 472 U. S, 797(1985).
  161. d at 821-22(quoting Allstate Ins. Co. v. Hague, 449 U. S 302. 313(1981)). .
  162. See LEFLAR et al, supra note 156, at 179-80.
  163. See Asahi Metal Ind. Co. v. Superior Court, 480 U. S. 102(1987);Intemational Shoe Co. v Washington. 326 US 310(1945).
  164. This is usually the case unless the court’s junisdiction is premised on mere service within the state. See Bumham v. Superior Court, 495 U. S 604 (1990).
  165. See Restatement (third) of Foreign Relations Law §§ 402-03(1987).
  166. See BORCHERS supra note 138, at 380-84.
  167. See id.
  168. See id;JUENGER, Multistate Justice, supra note 29, at 117-18.
  169. See BORCHERS, supra note 138, at 380-84 Bul see, eg, Schultz v. Boy Scouts, 480 N. E 2d 679(N. Y. 1985) (applying New Jersey charitable immunity law);Neumeier v. Kuchner, 286 N. E. 2d 454 (N. Y. 1972)(applying Ontario guest statute). .
  170. See supra notes 139-141 and accompanying text. .
  171. See supra notes 142-143 and accompanying text. .
  172. See supra note 138 and accompanying text. .
  173. See, eg. , Tramontana v. S. A. Empresa de Viacao Acrea Rio Grandense, 350 F. 2d 468 (D. C. Cir. 1965), Cipolla v Shaposka, 267 A. 2d 854 (Pa. 1970), see also supra note 169.
  174. See CRAMTON el al. , supra note 107. at 681-91. .
  175. See Andreas F. LowENFEI D, Conflict of Laws. Federal. State. and Intemational Perspectives(2d ed. 1998). SYMEONIDES et al, supra note 107.
  176. See Symeon C. SYMEONIDES, Private International Law ai the End of the Twenty-Ninth Century. Progress or Regress?, 59 La. L Rev. (forthcoming 1999).
  177. See Mathias REIMANN, Conflict of Laws in Westem Europe:A Guide Through the Jungle(1995).
  178. Von MEHREN, supra note 2, at 35.
© 2017.
Todos los Derechos Reservados a la Academia Mexicana de
Derecho Internacional Privado y Comparado A.C.